INTRODUCTION
The
Republic of Plato is the longest of his works with the exception of the Laws,
and is certainly the greatest of them. It was written around 380BC, concerning
justice and other character such as just city state and a just man. In
order to understand justice according to Plato, it is helpful to first
understand the conditions of Athens at the time. The Athenian democracy was on
the verge of ruin. They were struggling to rebuild from their defeat by Sparta.
Athenian citizens, to include Socrates, were growing critical of democracy as a
form of government
Plato in his philosophy gives very important
place to the idea of justice. He used the Greek word "Dikaisyne" for
justice which comes very near to the work 'morality' or 'righteousness', it
properly includes within it the whole duty of man. It also covers the whole
field of the individual's conduct in so far as it affects others. Plato
contended that justice is the quality of soul, in virtue of which men set aside
the irrational desire to taste every pleasure and to get a selfish satisfaction
out of every object and accommodated themselves to the discharge of a single
function for the general benefit. This paper explains the idea of Plato’s
justice in his book “The Republic”.
PLATO
BACKGROUND
Due to a lack of primary sources from the
time period, much of Plato's life has been constructed by scholars through his
writings and the writings of contemporaries and classical historians.
Traditional history estimates Plato's birth was around 427 B.C., but more
modern scholars, tracing later events in his life, believe he was born between
424 and 423 B.C. Both of his parents came from the Greek aristocracy. Born circa 428 B.C., ancient Greek philosopher
Plato was a student of Socrates and a teacher of Aristotle. His writings explored justice, beauty and
equality, and also contained discussions in aesthetics, political philosophy,
theology, cosmology, epistemology and the philosophy of language. Plato founded
the Academy in Athens, one of the first
institutions of higher learning in the Western world. He died in Athens circa
347 B.C.
THE THEORY AND ANALYSIS OF JUSTICE IN PLATO’S BOOK THE REPUBLIC
In Book I, Socrates
entertains two distinct definitions of justice. The first is provided by
Polermarchus, who suggests that justice is "doing good to your friends and
harm to your enemies." The definition, which is a version of
conventionally morality, is considered. Very soon though, its faults are
clearly apparent. It is far to relative to serve as a formulation of the
justice. Moreover, its individual terms are vulnerable; that is to say, how
does one know who is a friend and who an enemy? And are not friends as much as
enemies capable of evil? And when a friend acts wickedly, should he not be
punished? And next, what does it mean that an action is good or bad? The perils
of giving credence to false appearances are introduced early on as a major
theme. It will be dealt with at length in the succeeding books. A second
definition, offered by Thrasymachus, endorses tyranny. "Obedience to the
interest of the stronger," is likewise mined for its value, shown to be
deficient, and discarded. Tyranny, Socrates demonstrates employing several
analogies, inevitably results in the fragmentation of the soul. Benevolent
rule, on the other hand, ensures a harmonious life for both man and State.
Justice is its means and good is its end. The philosophers continue the debate
in Book II by introducing a new definition that belongs more to political
philosophy than pure philosophy: that justice is a legally enforced compromise
devised for the mutual protection of citizens of a state. In other words,
justice is a fabrication of the State that prevents citizens from harming one
another. Socrates is certainly up to the challenge.( Charles H. (2004).
Plato tries to seek answers
to these question; why do men behave justly? Is it because they fear societal
punishment? Are they trembling before notions of divine retribution? Do the
stronger elements of society scare the weak into submission in the name of law?
Or do men behave justly because it is good for them to do so? Is justice,
regardless of its rewards and punishments, a good thing in and of itself? How
do we define justice? Plato sets out to answer these questions in The Republic. He wants to define
justice, and to define it in such a way as to show that justice is worthwhile
in and of itself. He meets these two challenges with a single solution: a
definition of justice that appeals to human psychology, rather than to
perceived behavior.
Plato’s strategy in The Republic is to first explicate
the primary notion of societal, or political, justice, and then to derive an
analogous concept of individual justice. In Books II, III, and IV, Plato
identifies political justice as harmony in a structured political body. An
ideal society consists of three main classes of people producers (craftsmen, farmers,
artisans, etc.), auxiliaries (warriors), and guardians (rulers); a society is
just when relations between these three classes are right. Each group must
perform its appropriate function, and only that function, and each must be in
the right position of power in relation to the others. Rulers must rule,
auxiliaries must uphold rulers’ convictions, and producers must limit
themselves to exercising whatever skills nature granted them (farming,
blacksmithing, painting, etc.) Justice is a principle of specialization: a
principle that requires that each person fulfill the societal role to which
nature fitted him and not interfere in any other business.
At the end of Book IV, Plato
tries to show that individual justice mirrors political justice. He claims that
the soul of every individual has a three part structure analogous to the three
classes of a society. There is a rational part of the soul, which seeks after
truth and is responsible for our philosophical inclinations; a spirited part of
the soul, which desires honor and is responsible for our feelings of anger and
indignation; and an appetitive part of the soul, which lusts after all sorts of
things, but money most of all (since money must be used to fulfill any other
base desire). The just individual can be defined in analogy with the just
society; the three parts of his soul achieve the requisite relationships of
power and influence in regard to one another. In a just individual, the
rational part of the soul rules, the spirited part of the soul supports this
rule, and the appetitive part of the soul submits and follows wherever reason
leads. Put more plainly: in a just individual, the entire soul aims at
fulfilling the desires of the rational part, much as in the just society the
entire community aims at fulfilling whatever the rulers will. (Debra 2006).
The parallels between the
just society and the just individual run deep. Each of the three classes of
society, in fact, is dominated by one of the three parts of the soul. Producers
are dominated by their appetites their urges for money, luxury, and pleasure.
Warriors are dominated by their spirits, which make them courageous. Rulers are
dominated by their rational faculties and strive for wisdom. Books V through
VII focus on the rulers as the philosopher kings.
Only those whose minds are
trained to grasp the Forms the philosophers can know anything at all. In
particular, what the philosophers must know in order to become able rulers is
the Form of the Good; the source of all other Forms, and of knowledge, truth,
and beauty. Plato cannot describe this Form directly, but he claims that it is
to the intelligible realm what the sun is to the visible realm. Using the
allegory of the cave, Plato paints an evocative portrait of the philosopher’s
soul moving through various stages of cognition (represented by the line)
through the visible realm into the intelligible, and finally grasping the Form
of the Good. The aim of education is not to put knowledge into the soul, but to
put the right desires into the soul, to fill the soul with a lust for truth, so
that it desires to move past the visible world, into the intelligible,
ultimately to the Form of the Good.
Philosophers form the only
class of men to possess knowledge and are also the most just men. Their souls,
more than others, aim to fulfill the desires of the rational part. After
comparing the philosopher king to the most unjust type of man, represented by
the tyrant, who is ruled entirely by his non-rational appetites—Plato claims
that justice is worthwhile for its own sake. In Book IX he presents three
arguments for the conclusion that it is desirable to be just. By sketching a
psychological portrait of the tyrant, he attempts to prove that injustice
tortures a man’s psyche, whereas a just soul is a healthy, happy one,
untroubled and calm. Next he argues that, though each of the three main
character types; money-loving, honor-loving, and truth-loving—have their own
conceptions of pleasure and of the corresponding good life—each choosing his
own life as the most pleasant—only the philosopher can judge because only he
has experienced all three types of pleasure. The others should accept the
philosopher’s judgment and conclude that the pleasures associated with the
philosophical are most pleasant and thus that the just life is also most
pleasant. He tries to demonstrate that only philosophical pleasure is really
pleasure at all; all other pleasure is nothing more than cessation of pain. .(
Kierkegaard, 1992).
One might notice that none
of these arguments actually prove that justice is desirable apart from its
consequences—instead, they establish that justice is always accompanied by true
pleasure. In all probability, none of these is actually supposed to serve as
the main reason why justice is desirable. Instead, the desirability of justice
is likely connected to the intimate relationship between the just life and the
Forms. The just life is good in and of itself because it involves grasping
these ultimate goods, and imitating their order and harmony, thus incorporating
them into one’s own life. Justice is good, in other words, because it is
connected to the greatest good, the Form of the Good.
Plato ends The Republic on a surprising note.
Having defined justice and established it as the greatest good, he banishes
poets from his city. Poets, he claims, appeal to the basest part of the soul by
imitating unjust inclinations. By encouraging us to indulge ignoble emotions in
sympathy with the characters we hear about, poetry encourages us to indulge
these emotions in life. Poetry, in sum, makes us unjust. In closing, Plato
relates the myth of Err, which describes the trajectory of a soul after death.
Just souls are rewarded for one thousand years, while unjust ones are punished
for the same amount of time. Each soul then must choose its next life. (Notopoulos,
A. April 1939).
CONCLUSION
Plato weighed in on his interpretation of
justice after hearing the different theories presented by Cephalus,
Polymarchus, Glaucon and Thrasymachus, While he generally disagreed with all of
their theories on justice, he did recognize that they shared a common
denominator: each one treated justice as something "external," a sort
of convention. Plato disagreed. He believed that justice was a "human
virtue," which has a foundation in nature, and that makes an individual
good and self-consistent.
Plato argues that a ruler can never be
unjust. Rather, he believed in just rulers who ruled via moral virtue.
According to Plato, a just ruler should not seek war because war is unjust. War
is inherently evil, and "The creation of evil is not an accomplishment of
justice, but a failure of justice." (Plato, The Republic, 360 BCE, pp.
15-16). Likewise, he also weighed in on injustice. "Injustice is the
fool's game. It destroys individuals, as it destroys states." (Plato, The
Republic, 360 BCE, pp. 35-36).
Maybe upon understanding Plato's notion of
justice, the question becomes whether or not this "inner morality" is
possible for the modern individual, as we seem to be increasingly more
dependent on "external morality," as described by Cephalus, Polymarchus,
Glaucon and Thrasymachus.
REFERENCES:
Kahn, Charles H. (2004). "The
Framework". Plato and the
socratic dialogue: The
Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge University Press.
Kierkegaard, Søren (1992).
"Plato". The Concept of
Irony. Princeton University Press. ·
Nails publishing,
Debra (2006). "The Life of
Plato of Athens". A Companion to Plato edited by Hugh H. Benson.
Blackwell Publishing..
Nails, Debra (2002).
"Ariston/Perictione". The People of Plato: A Prosopography of
Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing.
Notopoulos,
A. (April 1939). "The Name of Plato". Classical Philology
(The University of Chicago Press)
Plato,
"The Republic." 360 BCE. Retrieved at
http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/republic.html.
Strauss,
Leo, And Joseph Cropsey. "History Of Political Philosophy, Third
Ed." Chicago: The University Of Chicago Press. 1987.
No comments:
Post a Comment